HAL Id: halshs-00348928
https://shs.hal.science/halshs-00348928
Submitted on 22 Dec 2008
HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access
archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci-
entic research documents, whether they are pub-
lished or not. The documents may come from
teaching and research institutions in France or
abroad, or from public or private research centers.
L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est
destinée au dépôt et à la diusion de documents
scientiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non,
émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de
recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires
publics ou privés.
Distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License
The economic value of virtue
Fabio Mariani
To cite this version:
Fabio Mariani. The economic value of virtue. 2008. �halshs-00348928�
Documents de Travail du
Centre d’Economie de la Sorbonne
Maison des Sciences Économiques, 106-112 boulevard de L'Hôpital, 75647 Paris Cedex 13
http://ces.univ-paris1.fr/cesdp/CES-docs.htm
ISSN : 1955-611X
The economic value of virtue
Fabio MARIANI
2008.101
The economic value of virtue
Fabio Mariani
PSE, Paris 1 and IZA
December 19, 2008
Abstract
We model virtue as an asset on the marriage market: since men value virginity in
prospective mates, preserving their virtue increases girls’ chances of getting a "good"
husband, and therefore allows for upward social mobility. Consistent with some histor-
ical and anthropological evidence, we find that the diffusion (and the social value) of
virginity, across societies and over time, can be determined, among others, by income
inequality, gender differences, social stratification and overall economic development.
This is a further example of how cultural and moral values can be affected by economic
factors.
JEL classification: D1; D31; J12; Z13.
Keywords: Mating; Marriage; Cultural values; Social classes; Inequality.
1 Introduction
Since Becker (1973, 1974), economic analysis has tried to explain several aspects of human
mating, family formation, spouse selection and marriage, the basic question being: "who
marries whom and why?". Therefore, we have now models that can help us understand-
ing a variety of issues, ranging from assortative matching of partners (in terms of human
capital, etc.), to inter-sex differences in the age at marriage (Bergstrom and Bagnoli, 1993)
and even the so-called mystery of polygamy (Gould et al., 2008). All these contribution
show that economic factors can also explain, at least partially, the historical evolution and
cross-cultural differentiation of family patterns.
I am thankful to David de la Croix and Jean-Marc Robin for useful discussion.
CES, Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne; 106-112, bd. de l’Hôpital, F-75013 Paris (France). Ph.: +33 (0)1
44078350; fax: +33 (0)1 44078231. E-mail: [email protected].
1
Our idea is that a simple model of marriage can also help explaining how the value of
virtue changes over time and across societies. In first approximation we use a narrow def-
inition of "virtue", identifying it with "female virginity at marriage" (premarital chastity);
in a wider acception, it might be also defined as "sexual exclusiveness", meaning that a girl
may have had premarital sex, but only with her future husband. Whatever the case, virtue
may influence spouse selection.
The idea of explaining the diffusion of virginity (or chastity) and its social value with
economic factors is, to the best of our knowledge, completely new. In fact, although the
"sexual revolution" has represented a dramatic break in the history of the family in West-
ern societies, the evolution of sexual morals and the way it can affect human mating has
usually been regarded as a cultural, ethic, and religious phenomenon, neglecting possi-
ble interactions with economic factors.
1
Still, if we look at the contributions of the socio-
anthropological and historical literature, we find a deep awareness that economic factors
play an important role in defining the value that societies put on (female) virginity.
For instance, Goethals (1971) observes that virginity is highly valued in societies where
women are looked upon as the property of their husbands: under these circumstances, vir-
ginity attains "market value" and parents, therefore, preserve their daughters’ virginity as a
means of protecting their own pocketbooks. In a similar fashion, Berger and Wenger (1973)
defend the idea that virginity serves the interest of women, helping them to secure a better
marriage, if they have little economic power. Broude (1975) shows that class stratification
is correlated with premarital sexual norms: where a society has a fluid class structure as
a result of achievable status, parents are expected to prohibit premarital sex to protect the
social standing of their daughter. More recently, Schlegel (1991) claims that the cultural
value put on the virginity of girls is, in large part, a function of the form of marriage trans-
actions. Taking a sample of traditional societies, she provides some evidence that virginity
is relatively more valued when marriage implies transfers of wealth between the families
of the bride and the groom.
This view of virtue as an asset on the marriage market needs not to apply only to tradi-
tional societies. In a study of contemporary China, Zhou (1989) puts forward that virgin-
ity is regarded as a "marketable asset", often the only one future wives can hold. Ortner
(1978) underlines that, in many (modern) societies, being a "good" girl increases the poten-
1
See Scott (1998) for a cross-national study on the evolution of attitudes towards premarital sex.
2
tial for personal status mobility: in this respect, virginity plays the same role of dowries,
enhancing the girl’s value for a higher-status spouse. Finally, Gonzalez-Lopez (2004), after
interviewing Mexican fathers living in Los Angeles, reports that, for them, "protecting their
daughters from a sexually dangerous society and improving their socioeconomic future is
of greater concern than preserving virginity per se".
Most importantly, in a well-known study of the historical evolution of the family in
Britain, Stone (1990, p. 401-402) claims that, in the 18th century, " ... the value attached
to chastity is directly related to the degree of social hierarchy and the degree of property
ownership. Pre-marital chastity is a bargaining chip in the marriage game, to be set off
against male property and status right". The female has then "a powerful lever to obtain
marriage". By consequence, as Stone suggests: (i) "the most sexually inhibited class in
the population is likely to be the lower-middle class of small property owners"; (ii) "the
rise of a class of landless rural labourers and urban workers without property or status
meant the rise of a class to whom virginity was not important, and foresight, prudence and
planning were irrelevant to their dismal economic future", (iii) "the developments of the
18th century, with the progress of enclosures, the amalgamations of farms, the development
of cottage industries and the growth of towns, were causing a considerable increase in the
size of such a class." Stone concludes saying that, therefore, "the principal cause of the rise
of illegitimacy in England in the late 18th century was (...) a rise of the proportion of the
propertyless with no economic stake in the value of their virginity". The change of attitudes
towards premarital sex was then dictated by a change of economic circumstances.
As for contemporary society, in the Western World the revolution in sexual behaviour
has been "anticipated" by some major socio-economic changes like, for instance, the in-
creased participation of women to the labour market, and an overall reduction of income
inequality and social stratification.
In this paper, we propose a theoretical model to explain that the incidence of virginity
may depend on (i) income level, (ii) the relative economic position of women with respect
to men, (iii) income inequality, (iv) the degree of social segregation, and (v) strategic inter-
action between social classes.
Central to our model is the marriage market. Potential partners belong to two different
social classes: the rich and the poor. Women value prospective spouses only in terms of
income, while men value also virginity, in girls. Mating is, to some extent, random: a rich
3
man can be matched, on the basis of true love, with a poor girl (although this is less likely
than him falling in love with a girl of the same census). Income is split between spouses
after marriage. Therefore, a poor girl can aspire to upward social mobility, if she is lucky
enough to be matched with a rich husband. However, virginity matters: if the poor girl
lacks virginity, love may not be enough to secure her marriage with a richer man, and her
place may be eventually taken by a rich maiden. This defines the value of virginity, as
the difference in expected after-marriage income between virgin and non-virgin girls, and
introduces a strategic dependence between virginity choices of rich and poor girls. All
results derive from this mechanism: in particular, all factors that lower the relative returns
to a good marriage (such as a reduction in inter-gender and rich-poor inequality) may cause
a reduction in the value of virginity, thus inducing less stiff sexual morals.
The paper is organized as follows. After this Introduction, Section 2 will describe the
structure of basic model. Section 3 will solve for the equilibrium, showing how the dif-
fusion of virtue depends on economic factors. Finally, a few concluding remarks will be
presented in Section 4.
2 The model
The characterization of the marriage market is crucial for our model. Not differently from
the existing literature, this market is based on a matching process.
2
2.1 Population, preferences and individual characteristics
The population of the model economy is divided equally between females and males, and
between rich and poor. This means that there are four group (rich women, rich men, poor
women, poor men) of equal size, which we normalize to one. The premarital income of
each individual is denoted by w
g,y
, where g = F, M and y = R, P.
For the sake of simplicity, we assume that everybody will end up married. Inside every
newly formed family, income is equally split between the husband and the wife, so that the
after-marriage income of the spouses is given by (w
M
+ w
F
)/2.
As in Bergstrom and Bagnoli (1995), we make the stark simplification that men and
women research different qualities in their prospective mates. The quality of potential
2
See, for instance, Nosaka (2007), Peters and Siow (2002), and Engineer and Welling (1999).
4
husbands coincides essentially with their income: women prefer to marry rich men. This
can be especially true in traditional societies. On the other hand, men value potential wives
on the basis of three parameters: love, money and virtue:
U = αL + βV + γY, (1)
with α, β, γ > 0.
The variable L denotes "love", it can take only the two values 0 and 1, and is assumed to
be random: a man can fall in love with a girl regardless of her income and virtue. This looks
like the "true love" hypothesis employed by Engineer and Welling (1999): it can encompass
beauty, physical attraction, affinity, etc.
V stands for virginity (that can be generalized to "virtue"): it also can take only the
values 0 and 1. An innate preference of men for virginity and/or sexual exclusiveness is
well documented. According to Buss (1994), men characterized by a preference for female
virginity enjoyed an evolutionary advantage, since premarital female chastity provides a
cue to the future certainty of paternity.
3
Stone (1990) puts it in a more straightforward way:
men value virginity in potential mates for it guarantees that they are "purchasing a new and
not second-hand goods" on the marriage market, and because they value "exclusiveness"
in the good they aim at buying. It also makes sense to assume that virtue is not equally
important in defining the desirability of men as potential marriage partners for the simple
reason that it cannot be assessed in males as easily as in females.
Money (relative income Y) refers to the fact that some of the after-marriage utility that
accrues to the husband depends on the division of resources inside the family; equation 1
can be thus rewritten as:
U
i
= αL + β
i
V + γ(w
F
/w
M
), (2)
therefore Y can take in principle any positive value, but it would not be unrealistic to as-
sume that 0 Y 1. Notice also that here we have introduced heterogeneous preferences
among male individuals: all men have the same preferences with respect to love and in-
3
To corroborate his argument, Buss also cite contemporary studies showing that the single best predictor
of extramarital sex is premarital sexual permissiveness. Not differently from the anthropologists, sociologists
and historians we cited in the Introduction, he firmly believes that the cultural variability in the preference for
virginity is heavily affected by economic factors, and namely the economic independence of women (and he
makes the example of Sweden).
5
come, while each man attaches a different degree of importance to virginity. To keep things
simple, we assume that β
i
is uniformly distributed among rich men, over the interval (0,α).
We also assume that α > γ: when choosing a mate for life, love is more important than
virtue or money alone, although it cannot be enough if the potential bride lacks both virtue
and money. We will come back on this assumption later.
U
i
is then the total value of a girl, as a potential bride, from the point of view of the
i-th man. It is important to underline that, while L and Y can be assessed before a man
starts dating a girl, V becomes observable only after two potential partners engage in a
relationship. However, for the sake of simplicity, we will assume that also V is observable
before marriage. This kind of assumption can be justified saying that, for instance, girls
cannot cheat (or decide not to cheat) about their virginity because cheating may eventually
lead to rejection immediately after marriage (in the Appendix, we will show that the results
we will obtain would not change if we assume that men can assess virtue only after dating
girls for a while).
Men and women enter the marriage market as soon as their earning capacity is re-
vealed.
4
At that point, all the relevant variables that determine the value of a potential wife
- love, income and virtue - are perfectly observable.
However, differently from income and love, virtue is not exogenous in our model. Be-
fore entering the marriage market, girls can decide whether staying virgin or not. Chastity
has a (utility) cost c
j
, that we assume to be heterogeneous and uniformly distributed over
(0, C
y
). However, preserving her virginity increases a girl’s value on the marriage market.
Every girl will therefore decide to remain chaste if the value of virginity exceeds the cost of
chastity.
2.2 Mating
Our model admittedly confer an advantage to men, and namely to rich men, who are free to
select their mates. This is not too unrealistic, especially in less developed countries and tra-
ditional societies. A marriage proposal made by a rich man will never be rejected since, by
assumption, girls value potential husbands exclusively on income. Therefore, we describe
4
In traditional societies, where women only engage in housekeeping activities and their resources are pro-
vided by the family, the bride is typically much younger than the groom. See also Bergstrom and Bagnoli
(1993), whose model explains why women on average marry older men.
6
the mating process from the point of view of rich men.
We have already pointed out that love is random. That means, in our model, that there
is an exogenous probability π that a rich guy falls in love with a poor girl; with a probability
(1 π ) he will be attracted by a girl coming from his same social class, so that it looks sen-
sible to assume 0 < π < 1/2: since people of different social classes have less opportunities
to meet each other, different tastes and levels of education, they have a lower probability
to find some affinity and reciprocally fall in love. Symmetrically, this means that a poor
girl has only a probability π to attract a rich guy. The parameter π can be interpreted as
a measure of the stratification or social segregation that characterizes a given society: the
lower π, the stronger is social segregation.
Therefore, on the basis of pure love, there would be π marriages involving a rich man
and a poor girl, and 1 π marriages in which both spouses come from the upper class.
Similarly, π low-income men should end up married with a rich girl, while 1 π poor-
poor marriages would be celebrated.
However, when deciding whom they are going to marry, rich men will also take money
and virtue into account. If for instance, one rich man falls in love with a poor girl who is
not virgin any more (call her LVY), he could consider to marry a rich girl he doesn’t love,
provided that: (i) she is virgin (LVY), and (ii) he has strong preferences for virginity, i.e. if
β
i
+ γ(w
F,R
/w
M,R
) > α + γ(w
F,P
/w
M,R
). If instead he loves a rich girl who turns out to be
non-virgin (call her LVY), he will still marry her because it would not be possible to find a
better match: given men’s preferences, and namely α > β, she will be preferred to a girl of
the LVY type.
Therefore, all wealthy girls who are lucky enough to be loved by a rich guy will end
up married with him, while only poor girls that are also virgin (LVY) can secure a "good"
marriage. On the other hand, poor girls that are not loved by a rich guy have no chance of
upward social mobility, while a rich girl in the same situation still has a chance to obtain a
rich marriage, provided that she preserved her virginity.
The role of virtue as an instrument for (upwards) social mobility is then clear: virginity
is an asset on the marriage market. The value of this asset can be defined in expected
terms; it will depend, among others, on male preferences over virtue, and on the competing
choices of other girls. Let us see how.
7
2.3 The value of virtue
For the time being, let us consider the shares of maidens among poor and rich girls (v
P
and v
R
, respectively) as given. Let us also define w
M,R
w and assume that w
F,P
= ρw,
w
F,R
= µw and w
M,P
= λw, with 0 ρ, µ, λ 1, ρ < λ and ρ < µ.
2.3.1 The poor
Consider now the perspective of the π poor girls, who happen to be loved by rich men.
Among them, the less virtuous ones ((1 v
P
)π) can potentially be eliminated as marriage
partners. The number of the actually dismissed ones depends on men preferences. In fact,
as we have seen above, rich men can decide to replace a loved, poor and non-virgin girl
(type LVY) with a girl who, although not loved, is both wealthy and virtuous (LVY), if and
only if β
i
> α + γ(ρ 1).
In particular, there will be a "threshold" male individual, characterized by β
i
=
ˆ
β =
α γ(1 ρ), who is indifferent between LVY and LVY. Men with β
i
<
ˆ
β will prefer to
marry the poor girl they love, regardless of her virtue; while those characterized by β
i
<
ˆ
β
will prefer a LVY-type wife (provided that there are any).
By consequence, the number of loved but poor girls, who are "at risk" is given by:
(1 v
P
)
γ(1 ρ)
α
π. (3)
Of course, how many of them will be actually replaced by rich, yet unloved, maidens
depends on the relative availability of this kind of marriage partners. For instance, all of
them will be replaced if v
R
(1 v
P
)γ(1 ρ)/α.
Taking this into account, the probability for a poor, non-virgin girl to marry a rich man,
is given by:
π
1
γ(1 ρ)
α
+
γ(1 ρ)
α
1 min
1,
αv
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)

, (4)
while her probability to end up married with a poor husband is:
(1 π) + π
γ(1 ρ)
α
min
1,
αv
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
. (5)
Losing her virtue exposes a poor girls who has been lucky enough to be loved by a rich
man to a double risk. First, he might be willing to replace her if he cares enough about
8
virginity. Second, she may be actually replaced by a rich maiden, if there are enough girls
of this kind on the marriage market.
Let us now look at the expected income of a "poor" girl.
If she is virgin, her expected income (which depends on the random variable π) is given
by:
π
w
M,R
+ w
F,P
2
+ (1 π)
w
M,P
+ w
F,P
2
, (6)
that is:
[ (λ + ρ) + π(1 λ)]
w
2
. (7)
The above expression means that, with probability π, a poor girl who manages to preserve
her virtue is able to raise her after-marriage income by the quantity (1 λ)w/ 2.
In case she is not virgin, her expected income is affected by the possibility of missing a
rich husband because of her premarital sexual behaviour, and amounts to the following:
n
(1 π) + π
γ(1ρ)
α
min
h
1,
αv
R
γ(1ρ)(1v
P
)
io
w
M,R
+w
F,P
2
+
+π
n
1
γ(1ρ)
α
min
h
1,
αv
R
γ(1ρ)(1v
P
)
io
w
M,P
+w
F,P
2
,
(8)
which, after substituting, becomes:
(λ + ρ ) + π(1 λ)
1
γ(1 ρ)
α
min
1,
αv
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
w
2
. (9)
Therefore, we can define the "value of virginity" (for the poor) as being the difference
between (7) and (9), that is the expected income gain attached to the choice of remaining
virgin:
P
π
γ(1 ρ)(1 λ)
α
min
1,
αv
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
w
2
. (10)
Notice that the economic value of virginity for the poor increases with π (it is higher if
there is less social segregation and then a higher - ceteris paribus - chance of social mobil-
ity), w (the absolute level of income) and γ (that, defining men’s preferences for income,
determines the probability of rejection). It is instead decreasing in ρ and λ: the higher the
relative income of the poor (women and men, respectively), the smaller the cost associated
to missing a rich husband. Finally,
P
depends positively on the aggregate behaviour of
poor and rich girls (v
P
and v
R
, respectively): a relatively high number of virgins, in both
social classes, increases the probability of rejection for poor and non-virgin girls, thus de-
termining a higher return to virginity.
9
2.3.2 The rich
We can now follow the same procedure to compute the value of virginity for the rich (
R
).
If she stays virgin, a rich girl can secure a good marriage with a probability (1 π)
(the probability that a rich man falls in love with her); moreover, she gets also a chance to
marry a rich man who does not love her, replacing a LVY-type girl. Therefore, the expected
income for a virtuous rich girl writes as:
(1 π)
w
M,R
+w
F,R
2
+ π min
h
1,
γ(1ρ)(1v
P
)
αv
R
i
w
M,R
+w
F,R
2
+
+π
1 min
h
1,
γ(1ρ)(1v
P
)
αv
R
i
w
M,P
+w
F,R
2
;
(11)
this expression, once we use w
M,R
w, w
F,P
= ρw, w
F,R
= µw and w
M,P
= λw, becomes:
(1 + µ) π (1 λ)
1 min
1,
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
αv
R

w
2
. (12)
If instead a rich girl has lost her virtue, she does not run the risk to be replaced if she
is "loved", but she loses the chance to replace a non-virgin poor girl, so that her expected
income is:
(1 π)
w
M,R
+ w
F,R
2
+ π
w
M,P
+ w
F,R
2
, (13)
which can be easily simplified into:
[ (1 + µ) π (1 λ)]
w
2
. (14)
Therefore, the difference between (12) and (14) defines the value of virginity for rich
girls, that is:
R
π(1 λ) min
1,
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
αv
R
w
2
. (15)
It should be noticed, among others, that
R
is a negative function of both v
P
and v
R
:
with relatively high aggregate "virginity rates", there will be less opportunities for the rich,
yet unloved girls to replace LVY-type girls, thus decreasing the premium on virtue.
3 Equilibrium
We have just seen that the economic value of virtue, from the female point of view, depends
on the behaviour of other girls on the marriage market. Therefore, premarital (virginity)
choices will be strategic in nature.
10
3.1 Virginity choices
Let us now recall that there also exist a utility cost associated to virtue. This cost is indi-
vidual specific; for the sake of simplicity, it is assumed to be uniformly distributed over
the intervals [0, C
P
] for the poor, and [0, C
R
] for the rich. These distribution are known to
female agents. A girl will decide to preserve her virginity if its value (
j
) exceeds its cost.
Therefore we can identify the endogenous shares of virgins inside the poor and the rich
female population, as being, respectively, v
P
=
P
/C
P
and v
R
=
R
/C
R
.
3.2 Reaction functions
Let us assume that C
R
= φC
P
and C
P
A, with φ, A 0.
Since
P
and
R
both depend on v
P
and v
R
, virginity choices of rich and poor girls are
mutually dependent: every girl decides her premarital behaviour taking into account how
many maidens there can be among girls from both social class. We can therefore write the
following aggregate reaction functions:
v
P
=
πwγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)
2α A
min
1,
αv
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
, (16)
and
v
R
=
πw(1 λ)
2φA
min
1,
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)
αv
R
. (17)
Alternatively, we can say that the reaction function for poor girls (v
P
v
P
(v
R
)) is given
by:
v
P
(v
R
) =
(
(1/2)(1 ±
p
[A 2πw(1 λ)v
R
]/A) if v
R
< γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)/α
πwγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)/(2α A) if v
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)/α
, (18)
while the aggregate behaviour of rich girls can be expressed as:
v
R
(v
P
) =
(
πw(1 λ)/(2φA) if v
R
< γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)/α
p
πwγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)/(2φαA) if v
R
γ(1 ρ)(1 v
P
)/α
. (19)
3.3 Equilibrium solutions
In this framework, we define a (Nash) equilibrium as a pair (v
R
; v
P
), such that no girl has
an incentive to revise her virginity choice (because otherwise her expected after-marriage
income would decrease).
11
Depending on parameters, we may have two different cases. Let us define:
ˆπ
2γφαA(1 ρ)
w(1 λ)[α
2
+ φγ
2
(1 ρ)
2
]
. (20)
If π > ˆπ (case (a)), the equilibrium is given by:
(v
a
R
; v
a
P
) =
πw(1 λ)
2φA
;
1
2
1
s
1
π
2
w
2
(1 λ)
2
φA
2
; (21)
if instead π ˆπ (case (b)), we have:
(v
b
R
; v
b
P
) =
1
2α A
s
πwγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)[2αA + πwγ( 1 λ)(1 ρ)]
φ
;
πwγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)
2α A
.
(22)
The situation is depicted in Figure 1.
V
P
V
R
0
1
1
PP
RR
E
a
(a) π > ˆπ
V
P
V
R
0
1
1
PP
RR
E
b
(b) π < ˆπ
Figure 1: Equilibrium
Notice that v
a
P
< v
a
R
if π < π
a
, where π
a
2φA/[w(1 λ)(1 + φ )]. If for instance
we make the parsimonious assumption that φ = 1, we have that the latter is automatically
verified since ˆπ < π
a
. Therefore, if π is relatively low, the diffusion of virtue will be
12
positively related to income, as historical evidence suggests (see Stone (1990), for the British
case).
Moreover, v
b
P
< v
b
R
if π < π
b
, where π
b
2αA/[wγ(1 λ)(1 ρ)(1 + φ)]. In general,
we have ˆπ < π < π
b
, so that we cannot exclude, in this case, that there will be more virgins
among poor girls than among rich ones.
Let us now see how the equilibrium values of v
P
and v
R
are affected by the parameters
of our model.
Concerning case (a), it can be easily seen that, for j = P, R: v
a
j
/π > 0, v
a
j
/w > 0,
v
a
j
/λ < 0, v
a
j
/φ < 0 and v
a
j
/A < 0. In case (b), instead, we have that, for j = P, R:
v
b
j
/π > 0, v
b
j
/w > 0, v
b
j
/γ > 0, v
b
j
/λ < 0, v
b
j
/ρ < 0, v
b
j
/α < 0 and
v
b
j
/A < 0. Moreover: v
b
R
/φ < 0.
Therefore, the diffusion of virginity is positively linked to π, meaning that stronger
social segregation, implying a smaller chance of upward mobility through marriage, de-
termines a weaker incentive to preserve virginity and use it as an asset on the marriage
market. In addition, virginity rates are decreasing in ρ and λ: both higher female income
and less income inequality imply a smaller value of virginity (because marrying a rich man
would not make a big difference), thus reducing the incentive to stay virgin. Finally, all
other things being equal, overall economic development (w) induces more chastity, since it
increases the absolute value of a good marriage. These results are fully consistent with the
historical and cross-cultural evidence discussed in the Introduction.
Men’s preferences also affect women’s choices, but only if π is sufficiently low, i.e. if
social segregation is strong enough. In particular, a stronger preference for "love", as well
as a weaker preference for "money", imply a lower risk of being rejected for a poor girl who
lost her virginity; by consequence they determine lower virginity rates.
Finally, the effect of women’s preferences (A and φ) is trivial: a higher cost of virtue
reduces virginity rates.
5
5
In this regard, notice that the cost of virginity might be affected, among others, by the effectiveness of
contraception. If the perceived risk of an undesired pregnancy after premarital sex decreases, the relative cost
of chastity becomes larger. Therefore, "technological" improvements in contraception, increasing A, would
encourage more promiscuity: this could be a complementary explanation for the sexual revolution, although
it cannot explain differences across traditional societies.
13
4 Conclusions
In this paper we have shown how the diffusion of female virginity can be affected by eco-
nomic variables. Using a very parsimonious mating model of the marriage market, where
preserving her virtue helps a girl to improve her odds of gaining a "good" marriage, we
have obtained results that are fairly consistent with historical and cross-cultural evidence.
In particular, increased female participation on the labour market, decreasing inequality
and stronger social stratification might be responsible for the decline of virginity as a social
value.
References
[1] Becker, G.S. (1973): ”A theory of marriage: Part I”, Journal of Political Economy 81 (4),
813-846.
[2] Berger, D.G. and M.G. Wenger (1973): ”The ideology of virginity”, Journal of Marriage
and the Family 35 (4), 666-676.
[3] Bergstrom, T.C. and M. Bagnoli (1993): ”Courtship as a waiting game”, Journal of Po-
litical Economy 101 (1), 185-202.
[4] Broude, G.J. (1975): ”Norms of premarital sexual behavior: a cross-cultural study”,
Ethos 3 (3), 381-400.
[5] Buss, D.M. (1994): The evolution of desire: strategies of human mating, New York, Basic
Books.
[6] Engineer, M. and L. Welling (1999): ”Human capital, true love, and gender roles: is
sex destiny?”, Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 40, 155-178.
[7] Gonzalez-Lopez, G. (2004): ”Fathering latina sexualities: Mexican men and the virgin-
ity of their daughters ”, Journal of Marriage and Family 66 (5), 1118-1130.
[8] Nosaka, H. (2007): ”Specialization and competition in marriage models”, Journal of
Economic Behavior and Organization 63, 104-119.
[9] Ortner, S.B. (1978): ”The virgin and the state”, Feminist Studies 4 (3), 19-35.
14
[10] Peters, M. and A. Siow (2002): ”Competing premarital investments”, Journal of Political
Economy 110 (3), 592-608.
[11] Schlegel, A. (1991): ”Status, property, and the value on virginity”, American Ethnologist
18 (4), 719-734.
[12] Scott, J. (1998): ”Changing attitudes to sexual morality: a cross-national comparison”,
Sociology 32 (4), 815-845.
[13] Stone, L. (1990): The family, sex and marriage in England 1500-1800, London, Penguin.
[14] Zhou, X. (1989): ”Virginity and premarital sex in contemporary China”, Feminist Stud-
ies 15 (2), 279-288.
A An alternative setting
In Section 2 of the main text we have made the simplifying assumption that virginity (V or
V), as a characteristic of potential brides, can be observed before mating, just like income,
for instance. We justified this assumption saying that the cost of cheating on one’s own
virginity might be very high (it could even determine repudiation after marriage).
In this Appendix we want to show that an alternative, more complicated, but more
realistic "timing of events" would be compatible with our model. Everything is based on
the hypothesis that, differently from income and beauty (that can affect love), virtue is not
immediately observable, and can be assessed only after the two potential spouses know
each other.
Therefore, since α > γ and V is unobservable, as soon as the marriage market opens,
rich men will start dating the girls they are in love with, regardless of their income. If
these girls display virtue (turn out to be virgin) they will decide to marry them. If they are
not, disappointed rich men will start looking for a better match, i.e. rich maidens, even if
they wouldn’t have selected them on the basis of "true love". Therefore, some (or all) LVY-
type girls will be replaced with LVY-type girls, depending on the relative size of these two
groups.
On the other hand, a rich girl who is loved by a rich guy, even if she is not virgin (LVY-
type), will get married because it would not be possible to find a better match (given men’s
preferences, namely α > β, she will be still preferred to a girl of the LVY type).
15
Once all rich men have found their best possible wives, the remaining girls will marry
poor men.
It is then clear that, also in this framework, virtue (premarital sexual behaviour) is an
instrument to secure a good marriage and eventually gain access to upward social mobility:
although the reason is different, both poor and rich girls who have defended their virtue
before the opening of the marriage market, can spend this asset to earn an advantageous
marriage.
16