LINCOLN MEMORIAL UNIVERSITY
LAW REVIEW
__________________________________
VOLUME 2 SPRING 2015
_____________________________________
HE WHO WISHES TO PRESERVE HIS LIFE AT
OTHERS EXPENSE SHOULD ALSO BE READY TO
GIVE IT UP FOR THEIR SAKE:”
1
HOW NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF
INDEPENDENCE JUSTIFY CAPITAL PUNISHMENT.
Nicholas Davenport, V*
I. INTRODUCTION
What gives a state the right to imprison a person?”
2
The simplest answer is that the person broke the law.
3
Justifying punishment, however, is not, and should not, be so
simple. It is generally accepted that our government is allowed
to punish persons who commit crimes.
4
Professor John
Bronsteen
5
demands that a “developed theory”
6
is needed to
justify punishment by society. The purpose of this article is to
J.D. Candidate 2013 at Lincoln Memorial University, Duncan School
of Law.
1
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT, AT 36 [1762]
(G.D.H. Cole trans., Barnes and Noble 2005).
2
John Bronsteen, Retribution's Role, 84 IND. L.J. 1129, 1129 (2009).
3
Id.
4
See id.; see also Kyron Huigens, The Jurisprudence of Punishment, 48
WM. & MARY L. REV. 1793 (2007).
5
Assistant Professor, Loyola University Chicago School of Law. J.D.,
Yale Law School; A.B., Harvard University.
6
Bronsteen, supra note 2, at 1154-55 (suggesting theories such as neo-
Kantian, Rawlsian social contract theory, and fair play).
46 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
provide a justifying theory for capital punishment in the
United States.
Generally speaking, the death penalty debate focuses
on whether it is right or wrong, and whether the United States
should continue to punish by death. Some people advocate for
the death penalty because of concepts like retribution and
punishment. Others believe the death penalty serves no
legitimate purpose and risks executing innocent people; for
instance, one scholar states that
[T]he death penalty is discriminatory in
administration in a country rife with
background racial discrimination, that it cannot
be fairly and effectively administered when
used as sparingly as it is usually used, that
having a death penalty creates too great a gulf
between the United States and other democratic
nations, or that there is insufficient evidence
that the death penalty has greater deterrent
value than life in prison without parole.
7
The focus on capital punishment involves whether we should
continue to have the death penalty. It is not surprising that
debates regarding capital punishment are generally focused
on whether the United States should continue to allow it as a
practice; but the far better debate would focus on whether, and
to what extent, there is a moral justification for the practice
that goes beyond the notions of “retribution” and
“punishment.”
8
For instance, some death penalty advocates
may believe that the death penalty is what some murderers,
i.e., the worst of the worst, deserve by dint of their
wrongdoing.”
9
However, the “he deserves it” approach is
more difficult to justify; additionally, one must subscribe to a
7
Claire Finkelstein, A Contractarian Argument Against the Death
Penalty, 81 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1283, 1284 (2006); see generally, Death
Penalty Focus website, http://www.deathpenalty.org/index.php.
8
See Finkelstein, supra note 7, at 1288 (analyzing the terms
“deterrence” and “retribution” as applied to the death penalty).
9
Dan Markel, State, Be Not Proud: A Retributivist Defense of the
Commutation of Death Row and the Abolition of the Death Penalty, 40
HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 407, 422 (2005).
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 47
moral basis in order to support the fact that the person
“deserves” death.
This article seeks to clarify America’s relationship with
capital punishment through one of the country’s most
important documents. This article will distinguish America’s
philosophy on capital punishment from the rationales of other
countries that also have the death penalty. Unlike in the movie
“National Treasure,”
10
the actual Declaration of Independence
does not contain a treasure map, but it does contain evidence
of a concept that reveals why America implements capital
punishment.
I. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE, THE “RIGHT TO
LIFE,” AND ESTABLISHING AMERICAN MORALS.
A. A RIGHT TO LIFE IS PROVIDED TO ALL AMERICANS.
The Declaration of Independence enshrines three basic
rights: life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.
11
“We hold
these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal,
that they are endowed by their Creator with certain
unalienable rights; that among these are life, liberty and the
pursuit of happiness.”
12
“The right to life is the only fundamental right, from
which all other rights are derived.”
13
The Constitution,
specifically the Bill of Rights, provides all other American
rights. Why would the Founding Fathers not list the “right to
life” in the Bill of Rights, but list the “right to life” in the
Declaration?
14
The authority of the Declaration of Independence is not
usually described as fundamental law; therefore, using the
10
NATIONAL TREASURE, Director Jon Turteltaub, Walt Disney
Pictures, Jerry Bruckheimer Films, Junction Entertainment, Saturn
Films (2004).
11
Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness, Principles of a Free Society
website, Ayn Rand Center for Individual Rights,
http://principlesofafreesociety.com/life-liberty-pursuit-of-
happiness/ last accessed Mar. 14, 2013.
12
THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE, para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
13
Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit, supra note 11.
14
Compare U.S. CONST. amend. I- XXVII, with THE DECLARATION OF
INDEPENDENCE, para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
48 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
Declaration as a primary reference in legal argument rarely
occurs. Some might argue that the Declaration is only an
emancipation document that does not carry legal authority in
the common use of the term “law;” however, there are those
that disagree. Professor John Eidsmoe, who is an attorney, an
author, and a professor of constitutional law and legal history
at Faulkner University’s Thomas Goode Jones School of Law
in Montgomery, Alabama, describes it as “fundamental law:”
[t]he role of the Declaration of Independence in
American law is often misconstrued. Some
believe the Declaration is simply a statement of
ideas that has no legal force whatsoever today.
Nothing could be further from the truth. The
Declaration has been repeatedly cited by the
U.S. Supreme Court as part of the fundamental
law of the United States of America.
15
If fundamental law is characterized as a base law from which
all other law extends, then the Declaration is perhaps
“fundamental law.” However, it is more accurate to
characterize the Declaration of Independence similar to the
Utah Supreme Court’s opinion regarding its Declaration of
Rights. Utah’s Supreme Court articulated that its Declaration
of Rights
16
“was never meant to establish a comprehensive or
positive law but merely to reaffirm various natural rights that
exist independent of any constitution.”
17
Nonetheless,
determining the role of the Declaration as it applies to capital
punishment is rather unique. At first glance, it appears that
capital punishment is in direct contradiction with a “right to
life.” To understand this dichotomy, one must analyze a
15
John Eidsmoe, Christianity and the Constitution: The Faith of Our
Founding Fathers, pp. 360-361 (1995); Earl Taylor, Jr., The Declaration
of Independence Part of American Law, Newsletter to National Center
for Constitutional Studies, June 1998,
http://www.nccs.net/newsletter/jun98nl.html.
16
UTAH CONST. ART. 1 § 1
17
Am. Bush v. City of S. Salt Lake, 140 P.3d 1235, 1283 (Utah 2006)
(citing Utah v. Gardner, 947 P.2d 630, 636 (Utah 1997).
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 49
concept that goes beyond fundamental law and into natural
rights.
18
B. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE IS A DOCUMENT
FROM WHICH AMERICAN MORALITY ORIGINATED.
Since a “right to life” is provided in the Declaration
and such right is a prerequisite to all other rights granted in
the Bill of Rights,
19
it is important for Americans to analyze the
need and justifications for the death penalty with all American
principles, especially the Declaration. “The Declaration
matters, and it is important that we bring to it the same level
of critical analysis that we apply to the Constitution and to
other legal texts.”
20
The Declaration is a document that reflects the moral
values of its authors, who were the founders of American
government. Principles stated in the Declaration are now the
roots of American moral code. “[T]he Declaration was an act
of all the American people, creating an entity, the United
States of America, which presented itself as one nation to the
world.”
21
The “right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness”
22
is a designation of morality. It is a moral
standard set forth by America at its inception to dictate what is
important. It is important to know that morality can be, and
often is, just a standard set forth by society. Morals can, but
need not be, universal concepts that are unchangeable. For
instance, defenders of the death penalty continue to refer to
moral desert,” which is a condition in which one is deserving
18
One law review author does not agree with analyzing the
Declaration of Independence solely through a natural law
perspective. He states, “The importance of the Declaration of
Independence to American law has been obscured by dubious
associations with natural rights jurisprudence.” Carlton F.W. Larson,
The Declaration of Independence: A 225th Anniversary Re-Interpretation,
76 WASH. L. REV. 701 (2001).
19
See U.S. CONST. amend. I-XXVII.
20
Larson, supra note 19, at 702.
21
Id. at 723.
22
THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
50 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
of something, whether good or bad, asreal, and not
infinitely subject to public manipulation”
23
The argument among Americans on whether the death
penalty is right or wrong should be discussed based on
perceived morals stated in the Declaration. However, how is
moral generally defined? Merriam-Webster Dictionary defines
“moral” as “of or relating to principles of right or wrong in
behavior.”
24
Morals, therefore, according to this definition, are
merely a standard of action set by a group of people.
Generally, morality is not just a single universal code; rather,
there are several potential definitions of morality, for instance
[w]hen a person simply claims that morality
prohibits or requires a given action, then the
term “morality” is genuinely ambiguous. It is
not clear whether it refers to (1) a guide to
behavior that is put forward by a society, either
one's own or some other society; (2) a guide
that is put forward by a group, either one to
which the person belongs or another; or (3) a
guide that a person, perhaps himself, regards as
overriding and wants adopted by everyone in
his group, or (4) is a universal guide that all
rational persons would put forward for
governing the behavior of all moral agents.
25
As Professor Gert noted, there are essentially two main types
of morality: normative morality and descriptive morality.
26
Descriptive morality is a type of morality put forth by a
society, a group, a church, or an individual for her own
behavior.
27
The set of people who subscribe to that moral code
23
R. George Wright, The Death Penalty and the Way We Think Now, 33
LOY. L.A. L. REV. 533, 537 (2000).
24
Merriam-Webster Dictionary, http://www.merriam-
webster.com/dictionary/moral, last accessed Jan. 20
th
2012 at
3:02p.m.
25
Bernard Gert, The Definition of Morality, THE STANFORD
ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, Fall 2012 Ed., Edward N. Zalta ed.,
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/morality-
definition/.
26
Id.
27
Id.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 51
live by it, and adhere to those morals.
28
Normative morality,
on the other hand, is a universal concept.
29
This type of
morality is a code of conduct that would be put forward by
any rational person under the same circumstances.
30
An
example of normative morality in terms of the death penalty is
a statement that the death penalty is immoral because “the rest
of the civilized world knows better.”
31
Indeed, it is possible
that ‘morality’ in the normative sense has never been put
forward by any particular society, by any group at all, or even
by any individual who holds that moral rules should never be
violated for non-moral reasons.”
32
Gert states, the only
feature that the descriptive and normative senses of ‘morality’
have in common is that they refer to guides to behavior that
involve, at least in part, avoiding and preventing harm to
others.”
33
There are two additional moral approaches that are
ancillary to Gert’s normative and descriptive classifications.
First, Deontology is one approach to morality; this is the best
approach, according to Professor Peter Brandon Bayer.
34
Professor Bayer contends that the Founding Fathers were
deontologists.
35
The Deontology theory asserts that
government is legitimate only if it governs according to
eternal moral precepts.
36
Deontology requires a sacrifice to
abide by morality no matter the circumstances.
37
Interestingly,
Professor Bayer offers that such a sacrifice is evident in the
Declaration:
38
For the preservation of those moral principles,
the Founders pledged their “Lives,”
28
Id.
29
Id.
30
Id.
31
David McCord, Imagining A Retributivist Alternative to Capital
Punishment, 50 FLA. L. REV. 1, 16 (1998).
32
Gert, supra note 25, at § 2, sent. 2.
33
Gert, The Definition of Morality, supra note 25.
34
Peter Brandon Bayer, Sacrifice and Sacred Honor: Why the
Constitution is a Suicide Pact, 20 WM. & MARY BILL RTS. J. 287 (2011).
35
Id. at 288.
36
Id. at 287.
37
Id. at 292.
38
Id.
52 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
“Fortunes,” and “sacred Honor,”
39
meaning
that it is the duty of all Americans-their “sacred
Honor”-to sacrifice, if necessary, their lives and
property to defend legitimate government.
40
A second moral theory is Consequentialism, which is a
moral philosophy that relies on the consequences of one’s
actions for determining morality.
41
Therefore, if the
consequence for an act is a “good” result, then such an act is
moral. However, while Consequentialism applies to capital
punishment, its application does not offer in-depth insight.
The referents of both labels [deontology and
consequentialism] . . . are usually caricatures,
used to oversimplify philosophical positions for
the sake of convenience and less innocently to
provide people with a plausible pretext for
rejecting ideas they do not understand.
42
Theories like Consequentialism and Deontology are overly
simplistic when justifying the death penalty and do not
provide a complete understanding of an all-encompassing
approach.
43
As such, for the purposes of this article, a more
encompassing and less restrictive philosophical approach is
necessary to answer the capital punishment dilemma between
the death penalty and the right to life. Natural rights
embedded in the Declaration of Independence serve this
purpose.
II. AMERICAN CRIMINAL LAW IS DICTATED BY MORAL
BELIEFS.
Morality in its various forms is so intertwined with law
that it is nearly impossible to evaluate each concept
39
Id. at 292 (citing DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 32 (U.S.
1776)).
40
Id.
41
Id. at 293.
42
Id. at 293 (citing Allen W. Wood, KANTIAN ETHICS at 259).
43
Id.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 53
independently.
44
One well known theorist, Immanuel Kant,
believed that laws lacking moral support are not law, rather
only commands.
45
Law is one method by which society
demands certain action that corresponds with morality.
When we credibly attempt to punish an offender who knows,
or reasonably should have known, that it was illegal to have
stolen, raped, or murdered, we are trying to tell him that his
actions matter to this community constituted by shared
laws.”
46
Basically, American criminal law creates and enforces
written law in order to avoid or prevent harm. Punishment for
non-conformity in an attempt to prevent harm is generally
summed into four categories: incapacitation, deterrence,
rehabilitation, and retribution.
47
However, these four
categories only penetrate so far when justifying punishment
for the death penalty; morality is the underlying theory that
provides authority for the notion that certain acts should
result in deterrence, incapacitation, rehabilitation, and
retribution.
48
Since morality is the basis of the aforementioned
punishments, the moral debate
49
is often the subject of
44
Id. at 369 (explaining that “Like morality, concepts of law ‘cannot
be understood in isolation from one another,’ although they can be
described discretely.”).
45
Id. (citing Allen W. Wood, KANTIAN ETHICS 108-09 (2008) (quoting
Immanuel Kant, LECTURES ON ETHICS, in Cambridge Edition of the
Writings of Immanuel Kant 27:273 (1992)).
46
Markel, supra note 9, at 427-28.
47
Mary Sigler, Contradiction, Coherence, and Guided Discretion in the
Supreme Court's Capital Sentencing Jurisprudence, 40 AM. CRIM. L. REV.
1151, 1154 (2003).
48
See, Markel, supra note 9, at 426. “In the past, retribution theorists
asserted that “the fact that a person has committed a moral offence
provides a sufficient reason for his being made to suffer.” Id. This
understanding of retribution as a purely interpersonal moral
doctrine has waned over time.” Id.
49
The moral debate extends in a multitude of directions. For
example, two popular, but contrary, views for defining driving
forces behind moral actions are utilitarianism and deontology.
“Utilitarianism, holds that morality is defined by the consequences
of one's actions or that increasing overall welfare generally equates
to doing the right thing;” Bronsteen, supra note 2, at 1130.
“[However,] deontology, [which] defines morality independent of
54 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
criminal law disputes, especially the death penalty, because it
is the ultimate punishment in criminal law. If the death
penalty changes, it will be due to a change in law, which, in
turn, indicates a change in societal morals.
Morality, when translated, becomes the law, which is
then written and enforced by a sovereign power. However, the
law operates by separation of powers through the executive,
legislative, and judicial branches. Morality’s ability to change
law can often be a lengthy process. This long process is
exemplified by the capital punishment debate through past
attempts to abolish the death penalty. The law can be slow to
evolve to meet social morals, especially in eradicating moral
concepts that are based on founding concepts of the United
States, like the “right to life.”
When law is or becomes contrary to moral beliefs,
social and political stability are undermined.
50
It is important
to keep laws updated in accordance with society’s progressing
moral code lest instability ensue,
51
otherwise the instability
results in unjust punishment of citizenry. However, there is
controversy as to what branch of government should adjust
the law to conform to moral preference. For instance, one
notion contends that the legislative branch should ensure that
laws reflect morality:
[t]raditional jurists contend that the positive
law is itself systemically moral and that judges
can and should decide all cases--including
those that present controversial moral issues of
liberty and equality--within the constraints of
the standards, rules, and precedents in the
positive law.
52
consequences and suggests that moral acts are done for their own
sake rather than in order to achieve any particular end.” Id.
50
Alice Ristroph, Third Wave of Legal Moralism, 42 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 1151
(2010).
51
Id.
52
Evelyn Keyes, Two Conceptions of Judicial Integrity: Traditional and
Perfectionist Approaches to Issues of Morality and Social Justice, 22
NOTRE DAME J.L. ETHICS & PUB. POL'Y 233, 233 (2008).
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 55
However, there is an alternative argument that the judicial
branch should ensure that laws reflect morality, which avers
that judges should, therefore, read the
Constitution ‘morally,’ i.e., they should
construe the principles of liberty and equality
in the Constitution in accordance with the
community's best construction of the moral
requirements of decency and fairness and
should implement the true democratic
conditions of liberty and equality.
53
Adjusting criminal law based on changes in society’s moral
fabric generally occurs in one of two ways. First, the
legislature can make or amend the positive law. This type of
law-making process is said to be in accordance with public
opinion because political representatives are elected to act for
their constituents. Second, the judiciary may alter criminal law
in some instances, especially those issues that involve
interpretation of the law. For example, the Supreme Court has
abolished some execution methods as violating the Eighth
Amendment’s
54
“cruel and unusual punishments” language.
55
The Court has held: To constitute cruel and unusual
punishment, an execution method must present a ‘substantial’
or ‘objectively intolerable’ risk of serious harm.”
56
Of course,
the previous statement is subject to broad interpretation. It
could be assumed that the Supreme Court may one day
abolish the death penalty based on changing morals. Perhaps
the Court will use the “right to life” language in the
Declaration to justify such an opinion; however, considering
natural law theories from which this phrase originates, such a
decision from the Supreme Court is unlikely.
53
Id. at 234.
54
U.S. CONST. amend. VIII.
55
See Wilkerson v. Utah, 99 U.S. 130, 136 (1878) (declaring
“disemboweling, beheading, quartering, dissecting, and burning
alive” are not allowed as execution techniques).
56
Baze v. Rees, 553 U.S. 35, 35-6 (2008).
56 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
III. MURDER VIOLATES A PERSONS “RIGHT TO LIFE,” BUT
EXECUTION BY THE STATE DOES NOT VIOLATE THE
MORAL “RIGHT TO LIFE CONCEPT.
At common law, murder was defined as “the unlawful
killing of another human being with ‘malice aforethought.’”
57
The intent to kill and the intent to commit a felony were sub-
categories of the single concept of “malice aforethought.”
58
At
its most basic description, murder is one person taking the life
of another through some volitional act. This act violates the
victim’s “right to life.” One West Virginia Supreme Court
Justice, in dissent, has described murder as “an ordinary
natural law crime.”
59
When a convicted murderer is put to death, there is no
violation of the right to life.
60
This dichotomy seems
contradictory at first glance but, in fact, it is not contradictory
to the right to life language in the Declaration. A person’s
“right to life” under the Declaration is different from rights
granted in the Constitution. The Declaration, as previously
established, is not the same type of legal authority as the
Constitution. The Constitution limits government action or
conduct against citizens; it does not apply to non-state actor
wrongs against other private citizens. Moreover, the
Declaration was not intended to necessarily limit government;
rather, it attempts to create a moral structure within which
both society and its government will thrive.
The Declaration is much broader than the Constitution
and applies to capital punishment differently. It can be
inferred that the Declaration imposes a duty not to kill on both
57
Schad v. Arizona, 501 U.S. 624, 640 (1991); see 3 J. STEPHEN,
HISTORY OF THE CRIMINAL LAW OF ENGLAND 21-22 (1883).
58
Id.
59
West Virginia v. Hobbs, 282 S.E.2d 258, 276 (W. Va. 1981) (Neely,
J., dissenting).
60
Not everyone agrees that a violation of the right to life occurs
when a convicted murder is sentenced to death: “Executions
undermine the very respect for life they purport to foster.” David
McCord, Imagining A Retributivist Alternative to Capital Punishment, 50
FLA. L. REV. 1, 13 (1998). While Americans subscribe to natural nights
by virtue of the Declaration of Independence, a person’s belief
system allows him or her to oppose such theories internally, while
society acts on an adjacent moral level.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 57
government and citizenry. The Constitution imposes a duty
only on the government not to kill unjustly -- unjustly
meaning through either deprivation of due process or cruel
and unusual methods of punishment.
61
For example, a private
citizen can murder another private citizen and not violate that
particular victim’s constitutional rights; however, such a
victim’s right under the Declaration’s “right to life” language
is violated. Such a moral violation
62
occurs under the
Declaration because of the natural rights theory known as the
social contract. From a natural law perspective, there is no
violation when the state seeks retaliation because according to
natural law that person’s right to life is voluntarily forfeited
based on the act of killing.
63
Notwithstanding natural law, there are other theories
that can justify punishment but that do not necessarily flow
from the Declaration. First, Utilitarianism offers one such
approach:
[f]or utilitarians the good that can be done is
preventing the criminal, by incapacitation, from
committing future criminal acts, plus deterring
other potential criminals, and minus the harm
punishment does to the criminal; but what a
criminal supposedly “deserves” is merely
revenge and does no good.
64
A second approach is retribution theory, which focuses
singularly on justice based on a theory of revenge. To put it in
Latin, lex talionis
65
or “an eye for an eye”
66
is the principle of
61
See generally, U.S. CONST. amends. V & VIII.
62
One commentator asserts that dignity is “the premier value
underlying the last two centuries of moral and political thought, an
essential ‘basis of human rights.” Leslie Meltzer Henry, The
Jurisprudence of Dignity, 160 U. PA. L. REV. 169, 172 (2011).
63
See ROUSSEAU, supra note 1.
64
Andrew Oldenquist, Retribution and the Death Penalty, 29 U.
DAYTON L. REV. 335 (2004).
65
“The principle or law of retaliation that a punishment inflicted
should correspond in degree and kind to the offense of the
wrongdoer, as an eye for an eye, a tooth for a tooth; retributive
justice.” Dictionary.com,
http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/lex+talionis.
58 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
retribution. Professor Oldenquist suggests that most people
are not well-informed when subscribing to the retribution
approach. Most people's reasons for capital punishment are
retributivist; they talk about deterrence because it seems a
respectable kind of reason that relies on crime statistics and
they don't know what to say when told retribution is
revenge.”
67
IV. AMERICAN SOCIETY CAN PUNISH INDIVIDUALS BY
DEATH, BECAUSE OF NATURAL LAW AND SOCIAL
CONTRACT THEORY.
Justifying capital punishment is difficult and rightly so.
One can use terms of art such as “retribution,” “deontology,”
“consequentialism,” and “deterrence.” However, these terms
are limited in application. They do not, for example, provide a
solution as to why America is in the minority of the world,
since most countries have abolished punishment by death.
68
Countries such as China, Iran, Saudi Arabia, Iraq, the United
States of America, Yemen, North Korea, Somalia, Taiwan, and
several others still retain the death penalty.
69
However, there is
a distinguishing factor between the United States and the
other countries listed above. Unlike the other countries, the
United States still has the death penalty because of natural
law, the philosophical concept that embodies various theories
that are mostly encompassed in a general theory known as the
“social contract.”
70
66
The phrase “eye for an eye” is generally used when referencing
Biblical scripture. See Exodus 22:24 (New Living Trans. 2d ed.).
67
Oldenquist, supra note 65, at 337.
68
Amnesty International, http://www.amnesty.org/en/death-
penalty, last accessed Jan. 20
th
2015 at 6:30 p.m.
69
Id.
70
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 13.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 59
A. PHILOSOPHERS WHO INFLUENCED THE FOUNDING FATHERS
“RIGHT TO LIFE LANGUAGE IN THE DECLARATION,
NATURAL RIGHTS, AND POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY THAT
OFFERED THE BASIS FOR AMERICAS FOUNDING.
“[T]he Founders inspired and justified both the
Revolution and ensuing fundamental principles of American
law, especially due process, on the best applicable precepts of
enduring morality they knew.”
71
Moral influence on the
Founding Fathers in large part likely came from theorists such
as Rousseau, Hobbes, Locke, and Mill, whose works offer
original and intelligent explanations into the American social
and political structure as well as America’s moral fabric. These
theorists believed in a concept known as natural law. “Natural
law theory is a label that has been applied to theories of ethics,
theories of politics, theories of civil law, and theories of
religious morality.”
72
One can look to the plain language of the
Declaration to derive evidence to support natural law’s
influence in the document.
When, in the course of human events, it
becomes necessary for one people to dissolve
the political bands which have connected them
with another, and to assume, among the
powers of the earth, the separate and equal
station to which the laws of nature and of
nature's God entitle them, a decent respect to
the opinions of mankind requires that they
should declare the causes which impel them to
the separation.
73
This aforementioned language and the natural rights concept
were successful in establishing a separation between America
and Britain. However, its meaning and impact established
more than just independence; it established a mindset, morals,
and a society. In order to fully understand the justification that
71
Bayer, supra note 35, at 328.
72
Mark Murphy, The Natural Law Tradition in Ethics, (Sept. 23, 2002),
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/natural-law-ethics/ (last
substantive revision Sept. 27, 2011) (last accessed Mar. 23, 2012).
73
THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE, para. 1 (U.S. 1776).
60 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
natural law provides for the death penalty, one must become
further acquainted with the philosophical ideas from these
natural law theorists whose voices resonated in the minds of
the Founding Fathers.
B. ROUSSEAUS “THE SOCIAL CONTRACT,” LOCKES “TWO
TREATISES ON GOVERNMENT,” MILLS “ON LIBERTY,” AND
HOBBES “LEVIATHAN,” OFFER CLARITY AND
UNDERSTANDING ON NATURAL RIGHTS JUSTIFICATIONS
FOR CAPITAL PUNISHMENT.
The social contract is exactly like it sounds a
contract. On one side of the contract is the individual; on the
other side of the contract is a collective unit comprised of all
individuals.
74
In his work, “The Social Contract,”
75
Jean
Jacques Rousseau offered two basic concepts upon which he
builds his well-known theory. First, each man seeks to
preserve himself; man in his natural state has free will and acts
to protect himself because no one else will protect him.
76
Rousseau’s second concept, the common good, offers a way
for each man to alter his method of self-preservation by
submitting through an exercise of free will to a civil body, but
in return he receives rights, and with those rights comes
protection.
77
In essence, self-preservation becomes
preservation of the civil state, and the civil state in return
offers to help preserve each individual through rights and
interests. “Each of us puts his person and all his power in
common under the supreme direction of the general will, and,
in our corporate capacity, we receive each member as an
indivisible part of the whole.”
78
The social contract takes man from a natural state of
anarchy and free will and provides a structured system where
free will impulses are tempered with human thought.
79
The
74
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 13-14.
75
Id.
76
Id.
77
Id.
78
Id. at 14
79
Oldenquist, supra note 63 (suggesting that humans are innately
social, as opposed to being social through adoption of societal
conventions).
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 61
social contract is mutually beneficial to all because the natural
state of man exploited the weaknesses of all men.
80
Under the
social contract, weakness is counteracted by collective action
and thought. Rousseau articulates that “only[] when the voice
of duty takes the place of physical impulses and right of
appetite, does man, who so far had considered only himself,
find that he is forced to act on different principles, and to
conduct his reason before listening to his inclinations.”
81
The
obligation of each participant under the contract is to conform
to the “civil state,” as compared to the natural state where
man only conformed to his own free will. “As nature gives
each man absolute power of his members, the social compact
gives the body politic absolute power over all its members
also[.]”
82
After man leaves his natural free state and enters the
civil state, there are boundaries of action; however, each man
still has liberties. But liberty to act is no longer unfettered as it
was in the state of nature. Rousseau argues that punishment is
required to preserve the civil state when man goes outside the
boundaries set by the civil state (i.e., when man violates the
collective morals).
83
Rousseau addresses the concept of the
death penalty directly in his work.
The death penalty is justified because the wrongdoer
has provided “consentto be punished or perhaps die for his
breach of the contract. “He who wishes to preserve his life at
other’s expense should also, when it is necessary, be ready to
give it up for their sake.”
84
As a result, if a person acts within
80
See ROUSSEAU, supra note 1.
81
Id. at 19.
82
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 31.
83
Other well-known theorist St. Thomas Aquinas agrees with
Rousseau declaring that “[t]herefore if a man is dangerous and
infectious to the [other members], on account of some sin, it is
praiseworthy and advantageous that he be killed in order to
safeguard the common good, since a little leaven corrupted the
whole lump.” Wright, supra note 24, at 554 (citing THOMAS AQUINAS,
SUMMA THEOLOGICA II (Fathers of the English Dominican Province
trans., 1929), reprinted in FRANCISCO DE VITORIA, REFLECTION ON
HOMICIDE & COMMENTARY ON SUMMA THEOLOGICA II-II q. 64, 240
(John P. Doyle trans., 1997).
84
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 36.
62 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
his former state of nature
85
(self-preserving) to the detriment
of another (for instance, through murder), then the civil state
must punish him, because the person harmed, and the person
harming had given up their right to act impulsively. The civil
state can act
86
because “by the social compact we have given
the body politic existence and life; we have now by legislation
to give it movement and will.”
87
In short, the act of
punishment is justified because the wrongdoer and victim
both consented to the civil state’s social contract for protection
and for punishment.
88
i. JOHN LOCKE
John Locke also shared Rousseau’s principles of
justification for punishment in a civil society. In Two Treatises
of Government, Locke explained: Punishment is permitted to
correct transgressions not for oneself but for mutual security.
89
More relevantly, “[e]ach [t]ransgression may be punished to
that degree, and with so much [s]everity as will suffice to make
it an ill bargain to the [o]ffender, give him cause to repent, and
terrifie others from doing the like.”
90
The former statement is
what is, in modern terms, called deterrence. Of course,
deterrence
91
is commonly used as justification for the death
penalty.
85
There is another perspective that believes detrimental human
action in the civil state is not a reversion to the previous state of
nature, but rather only a skewed action under the civil state. For
example, “To say that the defendant, at the time of the offense, was
operating at a sub-human, animalistic level
and yet engaged in
premeditation and deliberation or malice aforethought is to indulge
in patent self-contradiction.” Wright, supra note 24, at 555.
86
Markel, supra note 9, at 432 (noting a more modern term for civil
state action and punishment is known as “democratic self defense”).
87
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 39.
88
See id.
89
JOHN LOCKE, TWO TREATISES OF GOVERNMENT 312 (Peter Laslett ed.,
Cambridge Univ. 1960).
90
Id. at 315.
91
There are skeptics on whether the death penalty has deterrent
value. See e.g., Walter Berns et al., The Death Penalty: A Philosophical
and Theological Perspective, 30 J. MARSHALL L. REV. 463, 468 (1997)
(stating “If we make the admittedly unlikely assumption that the
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 63
Locke also addressed retribution, insinuating that in
the state of nature, a type of vigilantism is necessary.
However, the right to punish a transgressor in a structured
civil state is turned over to the government. Locke explains the
civil state’s collective protection scheme: “[e]xecution of the
[l]aw of [n]ature is in that state, put into every [m]an’s hands,
whereby everyone has a right to punish the transgressors of
that [l]aw to such a [d]egree, as may hinder its [v]iolation.”
92
The individual right of retribution that existed in the state of
nature no longer exists and is replaced with a right to punish
in the civil state. The right to punish becomes more complex in
the civil state, as compared to the state of nature. In the state of
nature, a wrongdoing was only an act against the person. In
comparison, a wrongdoing in the civil state is a crime both
against the person and the body politic, but the wrong can
only be righted by the body politic, which seeks punishment
on behalf of the victim and all others in society.
93
ii. JOHN STUART MILL
In his work, On Liberty,
94
John Stuart Mill also explored
the body politic. For instance, does man give up all rights to
the civil body to seek retribution? Mill articulated an answer
this way:
[e]veryone who receives the protection of
society owes a return for the benefit, and the
fact of living in society renders it indispensable
that each should be bound to observe a certain
line of conduct toward the rest. The conduct
consists, first, in not injuring the interest of
another; or rather certain interests, which either
by express legal provision or by tacit
number of murderers is equal to the number of murders, this means
that 99.9 percent of the murderers are not, or have not been,
executed, which is not much of a ‘message.’”).
92
LOCKE, supra note 90, at 312.
93
Id.
94
JOHN STUART MILL, ON LIBERTY [1859] (Charles W. Elliot ed., 2004).
64 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
understanding, ought to be considered as
rights.
95
It appears that Mill agrees with Locke’s perspective that action
by individuals who injure others is not allowed; further, it
appears that Mill agrees with Locke’s perspective that the
benefit for exercising restraint of personal vigilante retribution
is “protection by society.”
96
Mill avers that society will attempt to control human
action by either, or both, a written moral code (law) or a tacit
understanding.
97
The most interesting aspect of Mill’s “tacit
understanding” language is that no collective body can judge
tacit understanding, but rather it is determined within each
individual with the expectation of consensus among all.
Unlike law, which is interpreted and enforced by the civil
state, tacit understanding is in each individual’s mind.
Therefore, two sets of moral code exist: one that is prescribed
by society, and another which is a moral code of the
individual. These sets of moral codes are similar to Bernard
Gertz’s descriptive and normative morality, discussed above.
If one, globally-adopted moral code (“macro morality”)
could govern all human action, then no crime would exist,
because all human action would follow the predetermined
morality, i.e., no one would breach the social contract. Man
cannot give up all of his state of nature impulses; such
impulses will often result in breaking the law, or in other
words, violating the civil body’s code of conduct. Therefore, in
regard to Mill’s issue, how much free will does man submit to
the sovereign? The answer is not enough to prevent breaches
of civil code (morals). Man’s state of nature still exists, and
reverting to the previous state of nature often violates the
social contract and must result in punishment. In other words,
breaching the social contract is immoral.
iii. THOMAS HOBBES
“The Founding Fathers were heavily influenced by
English philosopher Thomas Hobbes in establishing America’s
95
Id. at 75.
96
Id.
97
Id.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 65
first principles, most notably the recognition of unalienable
rights, the social compact, and limited government.”
98
Hobbes
was a natural law theorist.
99
The paradigmatic natural law view holds that
(1) the natural law is given by God; (2) it is
naturally authoritative over all human beings;
and (3) it is naturally knowable by all human
beings. Further, it holds that (4) the good is
prior to the right, that (5) right action is action
that responds nondefectively to the good, that
(6) there are a variety of ways in which action
can be defective with respect to the good, and
that (7) some of these ways can be captured and
formulated as general rules.
100
In his work, Leviathan, Hobbes creates a metaphor for the civil
state in the form of an artificial man with arms, legs, and a
head.
101
Each part of the artificial man, which Hobbes called
the “leviathan,” performs the functions of the state.
102
Every
part of the “leviathan” is made up of each person in that state,
and each person has desires and reason. The good of man
corresponds with the good of the state.
[T]he Hobbesian view what is good is what is
desired, Hobbes thinks that humans are
similarly constructed so that for each human
(when he or she is properly biologically
functioning) his or her central aim is the
avoidance of violent death.
103
Thus Hobbes is
98
Michael Warren, America’s Survival Guide,
http://www.americassurvivalguide.com/thomas_hobbes.php
99
Murphy, supra note 73, at § 2.1.
100
Murphy, supra note 73 at § 1.4.
101
THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN PARTS I & II, (A.P. Martinich ed.
2005).
102
Id. at 9.
103
Similar to Hobbes’ “violent death” terminology, Nancy Bothne,
Midwest Director for Amnesty International, says that each person
has the “right to be free of fear.” Berns et al., supra note 90, at 471
(“To be free from fear is a concept that is a pretty incredible concept.
66 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
able to build his entire natural law theory
around a single good, the good of self-
preservation, which is so important to human
life that exceptionlessly binding precepts can be
formulated with reference to its achievement.
104
Similar to Rousseau, Hobbes takes the position that self-
preservation is the most important element of human action. It
is simple logic to connect between murder (the act of taking
another’s life) and the violation of natural law.
Robert Kraynak, a professor at Colgate University,
believes that Hobbes’ theory of natural law gave citizens a
standard for determining if the written laws and customs of
their nation or any other nation were just or unjust, right or
wrong, human or inhumane.”
105
Kraynak submits that
Hobbes’ theory of natural law has translated into what is now
called “liberties or rights.”
106
Therefore, the notion of self-
preservation at the natural law level has now been converted
into a right or liberty to individual life.”
107
The Declaration of
Independence contains this right. “We hold these truths to be
self-evident: that all men are created equal; that they are
endowed, by their Creator, with certain unalienable rights;
that among these are life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness.”
108
A violation of a person’s “right to life” is a breach of
the social contract and violates natural law. The United States
adopted natural law in the Declaration as a set of morals.
Consequently, capital punishment is morally justified through
natural law according to the previously discussed theorists.
109
It deals not only with a relationship of the state to individuals, but
with individuals to individuals.”).
104
Murphy, supra note 73, at 2.1.
105
Robert P. Kraynak, Thomas Hobbes: From Classical Natural Law to
Modern Natural Rights; Natural Law, Natural Rights, and American
Constitution website, http://www.nlnrac.org/earlymodern/hobbes.
106
Id.
107
See id.
108
THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
109
Contra Kleven Thomas, Is Capital Punishment Immoral Even If It
Deters Murder? 46 SANTA CLARA L. REV. 599 (2006) (concluding “…
capital punishment is immoral even if it does deter murder.”)
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 67
The Founders did not make up the right to life. Rather,
the concept was borrowed from theorists such as Thomas
Hobbes. In short, the Founders did not create natural rights,
but adopted them. Quite the contrary, natural rights have
created and shaped the United States into its current form: one
that allows the death penalty.
V. THE CONTRACTARIAN VIEW VERSUS SOCIAL CONTRACT
THEORY MORAL JUSTIFICATION OF CAPITAL
PUNISHMENT.
There is minimal authority for justification theories
regarding punishment outside the well-known death penalty
justifications.
The absence of any well-developed
contractarian theory of punishment seems all
the more puzzling in light of two salient facts:
First, there is a robust contractarian tradition
that emerged in seventeenth century political
philosophy, first with the writings of Thomas
Hobbes, later in the Enlightenment version of
this same tradition in the writings of Locke and
Rousseau . . . .”
110
Perhaps the absence of the contractarian viewpoint in
American capital punishment discourse is most unusual
because of its origin and relation to beginning principles of the
United States.
A. MORAL JUSTIFICATION
Punishment under a contractarian theory is generally
easier to understand than other concepts that operate with
death penalty arguments, such as retribution theory
111
or
religious theories. The act of punishment needs moral
110
Claire Finkelstein, Punishment as a Contract, 8 OHIO ST. J. CRIM. L.
319, 322 (2011).
111
See Markel, supra note 9, at 423.
68 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
support.
112
Contractarian theory provides support for
punishment in a different manner than other theories.
113
The
basic nature of a contract is that the obligation is either
fulfilled or unfulfilled, and if it is unfulfilled, action may be
taken to rectify the breach.
114
However, a source of morality
must be added to a basic contract viewpoint for there to be
moral support for punishment. Of course, in the case of
American capital punishment, this article establishes that the
Declaration of Independence offers a moral element to the
social contract view of punishment.
The contractarian view espoused by Claire Finkelstein
in the article Punishment as Contract is different from an
argument for social contract justification.
115
Finkelstein says
that it is unlikely that rational contractors would accept the
death penalty.”
116
Essentially, a contractarian view presumes
voluntary entry into a contract.
117
This article is unique from
Finkelstein’s assertion of punishment based on contract,
because pure contractarian view lacks moral justification
compared with social contract theory developed in the
Declaration of Independence. Finklestein is correct in her
assertion that “rational agents simply do not regard losing
their lives for the sake of protecting their property as a trade-
off worth making.”
118
This would not make sense either for
Rousseau or Hobbes because it would preclude the basic
notions of “self preservation”
119
and “avoidance of violent
death.
120
The social contract is assumed by the fact one is
alive. Therefore, an American citizen does not enter the social
contract voluntarily; rather it is inherently part of being born
an American citizen. While Finkelstein’s contractarian view is
similar to social contract theory, there are important
differences that differentiate social contract theory under the
112
Finkelstein, supra note 108, at 324 (stating “[t]he practice of
punishment therefore stands in need of justification if the
background moral objections to it are to be overridden.”).
113
Id.
114
Id.
115
Id. at 324-25.
116
Id. at 335.
117
See id. at 324.
118
Id. at 335.
119
ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 3, 5, 13.
120
HOBBES, supra note 97, at part 1, ch. 13.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 69
Declaration from pure contract theory flaws, such as lacking a
moral foundation or origin and lacking consent to enter the
contract because consent is assumed in social contract
theory.
121
B. CASE EXAMPLES OF THE “RIGHT TO LIFE,” SOCIAL
CONTRACT THEORY, AND JUSTIFIED PUNISHMENT.
The effect of natural rights, specifically social contract
theory, on the “right to life” is that they transform the “right to
life” from a plain language interpretation to a term of art.
Basically, the “right to life” is conditional-- not unconditional.
For example, the defendant in Kansas v. Kleypas,
122
who
appealed to the Kansas Supreme Court, argued that his “right
to life”
123
under the Kansas Constitution would be violated by
the death penalty. In his argument, the defendant
distinguished his “right to life” from a right to due process
guaranteed by the Fourteenth Amendment.
124
The defendant
further argued that “our [Kansas] state constitution simply
does not contemplate the taking of a life by the State under
any circumstances.”
125
He contends that the Kansas
Constitution confers upon him an absolute “right to life.”
126
However, the Court rejected his argument, stating that “[the]
argument, though somewhat novel, has been soundly rejected
by other state courts.”
127
Most interestingly, the court noted
that the defendant’s absolute “right to life” argument
“stretches” the language of the Kansas Constitution outside of
its intended meaning, and such an argument is not within the
121
See ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 13.
122
Kansas v. Kleypas, 40 P.3d 139, 252-53 (Kan. 2001) (overruled as to
some conclusions of law but not the “right to life” conclusion stated
in this text) (overruling recognized by Kansas v. Marsh, 548 U.S. 163
(2006)).
123
Kleypas, 40 P.3d at 252-53 (citing KAN. CONST. BILL OF RIGHTS § 1
(“All men are possessed of equal and inalienable natural rights,
among which are life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.”).
124
See U.S. CONST. amend. XIV.
125
Kleypas, 40 P.3d at 253.
126
Id.
127
Id.; see, e.g., Ruiz v. Arkansas, 772 S.W.2d 297 (Ark. 1989);
Missouri v. Newlon, 627 S.W.2d 606, 612-13 (Mo. 1982); Slaughter v.
Oklahoma, 950 P.2d 839, 861-62 (Okla. Crim. App. 1997).
70 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
spirit or letter of the language.
128
This conclusion leads one to
infer that other Supreme Courts would conclude similarly
when presented with the same question.
One dissenting judge in Rhode Island v. Blood
mischaracterized natural law and its application to murder. In
this Rhode Island case, the defendant killed a family
member.
129
The dissenting judge declared that killing a family
member is a “gross violation of the natural law.”
130
This
characterization in the context of this article is inaccurate for
two reasons. First, a gross violation of natural law does not
exist; there is either a violation of natural law or no violation at
all. Secondly, under natural law and the “right to life,” there is
no difference between murdering a family member and
murdering any other person in society everyone has a right
to live, even the murderer himself, until, of course, he or she
commits the murder and breaches the social contract.
The main purpose of the social contract is protection.
Everyone benefits from protection of the civil state. There are
two obvious instances that highlight the moral justification of
capital punishment through the context of natural rights. First,
capital punishment for murderers of law enforcement officials
is morally justified because police are necessary for self-
preservation under the civil state. The act of murdering a
police officer under Hobbes’ view is like severing the hand of
the Leviathan or the “artificial man.”
131
Essentially, the police
provide the protection that a person would have provided on
his or her own under the state of nature. However, it is a better
exchange for everyone to defend each other through a civil
body rather than trying to preserve ourselves alone.
Another obvious example that justifies punishment by
death via the social contract would be killing a person who is
weaker, such as a child. A child enters the world and bargains
for safety, protection, or in the event that protection fails,
retribution, in exchange for his or her relinquishment of free
will under the state of nature discussed by Hobbes and
Rousseau.
128
Kleypas, 40 P.3d at 253.
129
Rhode Island v. Blood, 37 A.2d 452, 454 (R.I. 1944) (Condon, J.,
dissenting).
130
Id. at 465.
131
See HOBBES, supra note 99, at 9.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 71
An example of a capital execution is the tragic case
involving Ernest John Dobbert Jr. and his daughter, Kelly
Ann.
132
Dobbert brutally abused Kelly Ann until she died.
133
Both Dobbert and Kelly Ann had a right to life, but when
Dobbert decided to deny Kelly Ann her right to life, he also
forfeited his own right to life under the social contract.
Therefore, when examining the “right to life” language with
natural rights concepts, Dobbert relinquished his right, thus
prompting the civil state to act
134
to both avenge the death of
Kelly Ann and preserve the civil state from further harm. The
Florida governor at the time of Dobbert’s execution
commented and described the connection between the state
and its citizens regarding such executions:
Ernest Dobbert has been executed because of
his brutal actions toward his own children. I
hope that this indication of the seriousness of
child abuse will be an example of the value
which the people of Florida place upon the lives
of infants and young people in our state, and a
measure of the lengths the people of Florida are
prepared to go to prevent and punish such
crimes.
135
Consider Locke’s position on such crimes: “each transgression
may be punished to that degree and with so much severity as
will suffice to make it an ill bargain to the offender, give him
cause to repent and terrify others from doing the like.”
136
It
appears that Governor Graham is essentially describing the
same idea espoused by Locke.
132
Dobbert v. Florida, 432 U.S. 282, 284 (1977).
133
Id. at 285.
134
The natural life, says Blackstone, “cannot legally be disposed of or
destroyed by any individual, neither by the person himself, nor by
any other of his fellow creatures, merely upon their own authority.”
New Jersey v. Kociolek, 129 A.2d 417, 420 (N.J. 1957) (citing 1
Blk.Com. 133).
135
Executedtoday.com,
http://www.executedtoday.com/2009/09/07/1984-ernest-dobbert-
child-abuser/, last accessed Mar. 31 2013, quoting former Governor
of Florida, Bob Graham.
136
LOCKE, supra note 88, at 315.
72 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
VI. THE CHRISTIAN INFLUENCE: CHRISTIAN FAITH AS AN
ALTERNATIVE MORAL THEORY IN THE CAPITAL
PUNISHMENT REALM.
This section offers one alternative moral influence to
the capital punishment debate. An in-depth analysis of the
Christian faith would encompass several works and require
extensive research and analysis. However, mentioning such an
alternative theory bolsters the natural rights argument as a
legitimate justification for capital punishment and it also
provides a more comprehensive understanding; further, and
more importantly, it provides a basis for another common
source of American morality to compare against natural
rights.
Throughout its history, the United States has
recognized a higher source of power God; for example, the
Pledge of Allegiance contains the phrase “One nation under
God;
137
“in God We Trust,” was first printed on U.S.
coins in 1864; the U.S. Supreme Court has, since the early
1820’s, opened session with “God save the United States
and this Honorable Court; and ever since George
Washington, during his inaugural oath, first added “so
help me God,” so too has every President since then.
138
Christianity has likely influenced the United States more than
any other religious faith.
139
President Dwight D. Eisenhower
espoused a high regard for the Declaration but considered it
second to the Bible: “Fellow Americans, we venerate more
widely than any other document, except only the Bible, the
American Declaration of Independence.”
140
When debating American capital punishment,
Christianity and its principles are almost always applicable.
137
4 U.S.C. § 4 (2013).
138
America Acknowledges God, Foundation For Moral Law,
available at, http://morallaw.org/resources/america-
acknowledges-god/
139
See, e.g., Holy Trinity Church v. United States, 143 U.S. 457 (1892).
140
Bayer, supra note 35, at 336 (2011) (citing Dwight David
Eisenhower, Report by the President to the American People on His
European Trip (Sept. 10, 1959), in WILLIAM J. FEDERER, TREASURY OF
PRESIDENTIAL QUOTATIONS 322 (2004).
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 73
Christian followers have a connection to capital punishment
because Jesus was executed. The story about Jesus’ short trial
and execution offers insight into societal desire to punish by
death and the political motivation which services that need.
The Book of Matthew, chapter 27, verses 11-26 describe Jesus’
sentencing:
[n]ow it was the governor’s custom each year
during the Passover celebration to release one
prisoner to the crowd anyone they wanted.
This year there was a notorious prisoner, a man
named Barabbas. As the crowds gathered
before Pilates’ house that morning, he asked
them, “which one do you want me to release to
you Barabbas, or Jesus who is called the
Messiah? The crowd shouted back, “Barabbas!”
Pilate responded, “Then what should I do with
Jesus who is called the messiah? They shouted
back, “Crucify him!”
141
It can be said that Jesus’ sentencing and execution is the
antithesis of America’s ambition for a capital punishment
process. An innocent man (Jesus) dies. A killer (Barabbas) was
released into society. No appeal or due process occurred.
Lastly, execution by crucifixion is cruel and unusual.
142
It would be difficult to argue that Christianity is not a
moral code. In large part, Christianity as a basis for morals is
more prevalent in the United States at least, consciously -
than natural rights; it is certainly referenced more often.
However, Christianity is unclear about its position on whether
it is for or against the death penalty. Should we forgive or
punish according to Scripture? America’s uncomfortable
association with the death penalty in modern times is likely
attributable, at least in part, to Christianity and its principles.
Christianity fuels two differing sides of the death
penalty argument. Consider the following passages and their
apparent contradiction to one another. The first passage is
from Exodus, Chapter 22 verse 24: “an eye for an eye, tooth for
141
Matthew 27:11-26 (New Living Trans. 2d ed.).
142
See In Re Kemmler, 136 U.S. 436, 446 (1890).
74 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
a tooth, a hand for a hand, a foot for a foot.”
143
Now compare
the previous pro-death penalty passage with one that endorses
forgiveness
144
instead of retribution: “Get rid of all bitterness,
rage, anger, harsh words, and slander, as well as all types of
evil behavior.”
145
“Instead, be kind to each other,
tenderhearted, forgiving one another, just as God through
Christ has forgiven you.”
146
The natural rights position is clear
on capital punishment; it is not only allowed, but required.
Christianity is ambiguous on the topic of capital punishment,
as evidenced by the ambiguity of various Bible verses.
While Christianity is the basis of numerous moral
discussions about capital punishment, it is mutually exclusive
in text. The language of the Bible is subject to interpretation. It
is difficult for opponents to discern whether or not one
actually believes the scripture and is enforcing it, or whether
that person believes in or against the death penalty and is
using scripture to support his or her position. As such, natural
rights are not as ambiguous, nor as controversial, as
Christianity. Furthermore, natural rights are adopted by virtue
of being American. Christianity, on the other hand, is not
adopted by virtue of citizenship; rather, it is voluntarily
adopted. In other words, a person can, of course, be an
American but not a Christian; however, one cannot be an
American and not be subject to natural law, because of the
Declaration of Independence’s incorporation of natural rights
and its involuntary social contract.
An issue arises when participants in the death penalty
process are Christians who subscribe to the forgiveness text as
the most important tenet of the Bible.
143
Exodus 22:24 (New Living Trans. 2d ed.); see also Numbers 35:31;
Leviticus 24:16-17.
144
For an interesting account of execution and the Christian Faith, see
e.g., Jill Jones, The Christian Executioner: Reconciling "An Eye for an
Eye" with "Turn the Other Cheek", 27 PEPP. L. REV. 127, 127 (1999)
(What made the Texas execution (Karla Faye Tucker) so dramatic
was the fact that the “pickax killer” was a born-again Christian); see
also Michael Graczyk, Tucker Face to Face with Jesus, ARIZ. REP., Feb. 4,
1998, at A1.
145
Ephesians 4: 31-32 (New Living Trans. 2d ed.).
146
Id.
NATURAL LAW AND THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE 75
In Florida, one criminal judge dramatically
highlighted the struggle that some practitioners
face regarding whether they can participate in
capital sentencing by writing a series of letters
to the public in the local newspaper. In one
such letter he declared, “[b]ecause God has
given me a new life in Jesus Christ, I choose not
to condone our use of capital punishment.”
147
Punishment under a natural rights theory may not correspond
with religious moral principles, especially for those charged
with the task of carrying out the execution. As such, it is
possible that man’s moral codes can contradict one another.
The dilemma then becomes which path to follow; in other
words, which morals to adopt.
VII. CONCLUSION
Summing up the death penalty in few words is almost
impossible; however, the following passage is an admirable
attempt. We pity him [subject of execution], but we also
appreciate the anger of his countrymen and the dramatic
necessity of his death. The dramatic necessity would appear to
rest on its moral necessity.”
148
This passage draws on the social
contract theory to find the death penalty is a necessary evil.
Social contract theory, when supported by the moral nature of
the Declaration, offers Americans a developed and unique
argument to justify decisions and actions surrounding the
death penalty.
As established previously, every American has a right
to life when they enter the social contract pursuant to the
Declaration’s language. However, breach of this social contract
through murder violates another’s right to life, as inferred
from Rousseau, Locke, Mill, and Hobbes, and subjects the
147
Jones, supra note 143, at 134 (citing Talbot D'Alemberte, Searching
for the Limits of Judicial Free Speech, 61 TUL. L. REV. 611, 639 n.154
(1987).
148
Berns et.al, supra note 92, at 469.
76 2 LMU LAW REVIEW (2015)
murderer to morally justified punishment.
149
Punishment is
necessary and consented to by the wrongdoer to accomplish
the key goal of self-preservation of all individuals in the state.
Therefore, the death penalty serves a purpose of “self-
preservation”
150
under the social contract by offering the
bargained-for protection guaranteed by the civil state in
exchange that Man leaves his state of nature.
Considering the Founding Fathers’ sources of
philosophical influences, the “right to life” is not absolute; it is
subject to forfeiture by the act of murder under the social
contract. The death penalty serves a necessary function under
natural law theory that adheres to deep-rooted morals of
American society encompassed in the Declaration of
Independence. Therefore, given the origins of America’s
founding, it is not surprising that America still has the death
penalty.
149
See Wright, supra note 24, at 535 (concluding the death penalty is,
under our social circumstances, not morally justifiable, even in
principle).
150
See ROUSSEAU, supra note 1, at 13-6.